The Banality Principal
By Aime Michel, 1973
Twenty-five
years after the first rumours, flying saucers are still a subject of
discord between the scientists. This in itself is a matter of thought.
When
a new scientific problem arises, and even if its solution is not
forthcoming, at least it does not take very long for an agreement to be
reached on its nature and the possible ways to describe the problem. And
if no agreement is reached on this, everyone soon recognizes that the
problem was not likely to be solved using the scientific method. One
then gives up, until the nature of the problem changes or until new
methods are discovered.
Nothing like that occurred with the
flying saucers. Although no agreement was reached neither on their
nature nor on the way of studying them, the researchers are increasingly
numerous to ignore the discredit which sticks to it, and to devote a
share of their time and their reflexions to this subject.
This
situation seems to be unprecedented. Everything happens as if what
started as a mere rumour now announces a developping change of
mentality, not only in the Western world, but in socialist countries
too, and even, it has been said, in China, since the fall of 1970.
To
understand what this change consists of (and perhaps to understand
where it leads), it is first necessary to remind the various assumptions
advanced since 1947 to explain flying saucers reports, and the dead end
which resulted from it. These assumptions were four:
1. Secret aircraft, American or Russian;
2. misinterpretation of known aircraft or natural phenomena;
3. Mass hysteria inducing a mythology;
4. Craft of extraterrestrial origin.
It
is on these assumptions that the scientists were summoned to decide.
And because they indeed decided within the framework of these
assumptions, they settled in the spirit of the public, which, more than
one quarter century later, remain their prisoner. And at the same time
as these assumptions settled in the spirit of the public a certain
number of simple and apparently obvious reasoning led the problem to the
dead end where it is now. Let us briefly summarize them:
Initially
(and this answers the assumption No 1), it is now quite certain that
flying saucers are not terrestrial secret machines. First because we
know, thanks to astronautics, of the achievements that the great nations
are capable. Nothing, in their arsenal, resembles even by far the
descriptions (wrongly or rightly) of the alleged witnesses. It is quite
obvious that if the Russians or the Americans had machines capable of
the performances described by the police officer of Socorro or the
peasant of Valensole, they would not ruin themselves launching million
dollars rockets, which, in addition, can miss their goal or explode. The
Americans would have liked to have aircraft able to fly silently at
Mach 10 and to be land vertically, noiselessly, in the Vietnam conflict.
An
even more convincing reason is that very detailed testimonies going
back to one century or more have been found later. It is thus necessary
to give up the first assumption.
Assumptions 2 and 3 are
certainly satisfactory for the mind. They do not require any scientific
acrobatics, no psychological revolution. They provide a suitable
explanation for what is published in the newspapers, that one should not
accept as true as soon as they provide extraordinary tales.
But
on another side, these assumptions never gave satisfaction neither to
the witnesses nor to the scientists having inquired directly with the
witnesses. Whatever the reason for which neither these scientists nor
these witnesses find the two assumptions of the psychosis and the faulty
interpretation satisfactory, their skepticism is a fact facing in an
irritating way the researchers sincerely eager to clarify.
The
most known illustration of this dilemma is the Condon report (1).
Condon, himself an eminent physicist, judges on documents, without even
interviewing one single witness, without going on location even once. He
concludes in the inexistence of any strange phenomenon, and anyone who
follows his steps (i.e. which believes in his capacity to decide without
direct study) follows him almost infallibly in his conclusion: there is
nothing.
But Condon had a team of investigators made up of
scientists just as qualified as he was. At the head of this team, was
Saunders (designated in the "Condon Report," p. 941, as the "main
investigator"). Saunders was, and is still now, professor of psychology
in the same University of Colorado where Condon is a professor of
physics. He has a thorough experience of the investigations. He thus
investigates. And he comes at an exactly opposite conclusion with that
of Condon, whom he disputed with glare. Following the incident, he
publishes a book rejecting the "Condon Report."
Previously, the
fight against the "judge" delivering his verdict based on documents and
the investigator who studied the phenomenon directly had already
occurred: in 1952, major Ruppelt, the person in charge of Project Blue
Book, had made a positive verdict, while Robertson, president of the
jury, studying Ruppelt's reports, issued a negative verdict. Same
contradiction between the higher authorities of the Air Force and the
astronomer Hynek in 1968, in front of the ad hoc congressional panel.
We
are forced into making a note of these contradictions. What is called
scientific certainty, it is the collective approval of the specialists
on a point in their specialty. The least we can say is that there is a
complete disagreement between the scientists having studied the flying
saucers. Let us notice that the opinion of the others, i.e. those which
decide without ever having studied the problem neither directly nor
indirectly, has as much value, but not more value, than the opinion of a
historian on a question of physics: a considerable value on the
question of the methods (which are common to all sciences), but a weak
or null about the questions of facts concerned with the specialty under
discussion, and for which the scientists who are not specialists are
simply part of the public and do not know anything more than the public.
It
is by examining the fourth assumption, that of the extraterrestrial
origin, that we can understand why the immense majority of judicious
people adopted the explanation by assumptions 2 and 3.
Indeed, if
one challenges the explanation by faulty interpretation and the
psychosis, the extraterrestrial assumption is the only that remains
available. However, it encounters insurmountable objections, as we will
see.
It is almost certain that human intelligence is the only one
which appeared in our solar system. Thus, the alleged extraterrestrial
machines presumably present above our heads must come other systems.
But, in this case, they must be machines that traveled huge distances
and for which the arrival in our neighborhood constitutes the success of
a truly extraordinary technical prowess. All calculations of mass
ratios, necessary time and necessary energy lead indeed to the almost
impossibility, or even absolute impossibility, if these supposed beings
do not come from one of the two or three closest stars (2).
Consequently,
if beings coming from elsewhere had carried out such a wonderful
achievement, it is unreasonable to imagine that they did it with the
only aim of performing some vague manoeuvers in front of a peasant of
the Lozere or an Indian of the Orenoque, and then disappear at once.
Such an assumption is insupportable. When abysses of light-years length
are crossed at the price of a fantastic expenditure of energy and that
results in the discovery of an unknown civilization, contact must
obviously be the outcome.
However, no extraterrestrial
civilization contacted humanity, it is a fact. Thus, flying saucers are a
nonsense, and whatever the difficulties to explain them in a
satisfactory way by hysteria, stupidity or ignorance, it is however
necessary to admit such explanation, since there is not the different
possible explanation. Admittedly, one will never prove the inexistence
of the Father Christmas and there will be always be simple-minded people
to prefer to believe in him rather than to hear reason. But here we
have a perfectly convincing negative argument: for Father Christmas, we
know that he wants to hide to please nice children; whereas as far as
extraterrestrial beings are concerned, they would inevitably let their
presence known to us, since they went out to look for us; they would
thus inevitably show themselves to us if they came here; they are not
seen; thus they are not here. On the other hand, human stupidity and
credulity are a well proven fact. And as they can suffice to explain
anything, the question is settled.
Scientists who believe in the
reality of the flying saucers precisely dispute that stupidity and
credulity are sufficient to explain it all away. But is there a
sufficient reason to enter their obscure research, with the risk to
waste a time which may be devoted to more useful activities?
Not
wanting to divert the reader from more serious occupations than hunting
for saucers, we will restrict ourselves to ask him whether he ever goes
to the movies, if he ever reads a novel, if he ever watches television,
if he ever meditates on certain enigmas to which he well knows that he
will never find an answer, in short, if he never loses a little of his
time to dwell some dream.
A prominent German scientist, Nobel
Prize, with whom we spoke one day about this, told me that he was too
busy to waste his time in this field. In the continuation of the
conversation, he told us that to distract himself, he played chess and
read detective novels.
So let's have the reader thus consider
this as a detective novel, a relaxation of the mind. He will then see,
having read this, if it is necessary to give it more attention. The
problem that we propose is as follows:
If an extraterrestrial activity manifested itself to us, how does science invite us to imagine it?
In
the absence of better, this problem is a decent police enigma: the
proof is that it already inspired science fiction books by the thousands
in all the languages.
Let's start with the inventory of knowledge which can be used for our reflexion. They concern astronomy, physics and biology.
1.
Astronomy: it is presently known that the Sun is a very ordinary star
that nothing distinguishes from many other star in our galaxy, in which
there are between 100 and 200 billion stars. It is also known that most
probably the planet procession which accompanies our star is not an
exception, but a rule: all stars acquire a planetary system during the
first million years of their life.
It is also known that the
structure of planets of the solar system, far from being an effect of
chance, is an ordinary consequence from the physical conditions reigning
in the environment of stars: planets very close to star are rather
small, telluric, solid, missing an atmosphere; distant planets are
rather large, fluid, cold, are surrounded by a thick atmosphere;
finally, the intermediate zone produces planets of the terrestrial type,
i.e. solid and surrounded by an atmosphere made of water, carbon
dioxide and nitrogen.
In the same way, therefore, as the Sun is a
banal star, the Earth is also a banal planet from the point of view of
physic, i.e. not considering life.
We also know that (except in
clusters) the stars are very distant from each other, their average
distance being of several light-years within the galaxies; galaxies
having dimensions being evaluated in hundreds of thousands of
light-years and are on average distant from/to each other of several
million light-years.
Finally, we known that space is populated
with stars of all ages. Certain stars die under our eyes. Others were
born there ten or perhaps twenty billion years ago. If the universe is
expanding, it perhaps started (in its current form) about ten or twenty
billion years ago. The Sun, aged of approximately five billion years,
thus lines up among recent stars. It is consequently the same with the
Earth among the whole of planets of the universe.
2. Physics: the
data of physics which interest us here are the relativistic laws. They
teach us that to give an unspecified mass, even very light, even reduced
to only one particle, a speed close to the speed of light, one would
need an infinite energy. No physical body can thus reach the speed of
the light. That means that the exploration of the universe by machines
is impossible, for the only crossing of the known universe would take a
time longer than the life of stars. The conceivable maximum way could
thus enable us to reach only the few closest stars.
3. Biology:
the most invaluable data of biology are those of paleontology and
geology. First they show that life appeared on the Earth right from the
start of planet, during the first billion years. Although it is not yet
known how the first living beings were formed, geological documents
attest that everything happened on the Earth as if the apparition of
life were a normal and automatic phenomenon wherever it can develop, not
requiring any miracle. The majority of the biologists think that it is
so. They especially give as argument the apparently universal presence
of aminoacids which were detected as well in space as in the models of
primitive atmospheres artificially created in laboratory. Some rare
biologists (Monod) believe however that the apparition of life is a
statistical miracle which occurred only once in the universe, precisely
on the Earth.
With paleontology we also learn:
a) that life started to evolve quicker and quicker towards more an more complex lifeforms, and this, to the human being;
b)
that apparition of man is marked by no discontinuity, the passage of
what we call animality to what we call humanity taking place in an
unperceivable way, and, as much as it is known, by the play of the same
laws as any other change;
c) that man himself apparently never ceased
to evolve; the laws of the genetics of the populations always seem with
work within current humanity, though moderated by the deceleration of
the selection.
Let us re-examine the problem of the long space flights now.
We
saw that science shows the impossibility of it. Is this demonstration
final? To claim this, it would be necessary to have the certainty that
the relativistic framework from where it rises determines the ultimate
limits of any reality.
Everything seems as if it were really so.
But it must be observed that it was always like that with science's
paradigm, at any time of its history. It was in particular thus in 19th
century, after Maxwell had made the synthesis of everything that was
then known. No conceivable fact could, at that time, indicate the
limited character of this synthesis, as the famous statement by Lord
Kelvin declaring that "physics has from now on a perfectly harmonious
unity, and is, essentially, completed," and that the work of the
physicists of the future would be reduced "to add decimals to the
already known results."
It is just as impossible to currently
show the limited character of the relativistic framework than it was in
1900 to imagine a breach within Maxwell's synthesis. So, for example, it
is impossible in the physics of Maxwell and Kelvin to allot a mass to
the electromagnetic radiation, and with stronger reason impossible to
imagine an equivalence between mass and energy.
It belongs to the
physicists and the physicist alone, of course, to speak about physics.
But the history of physics invites an historical and philosophical
reflexion. If the philosopher and the historian do not have anything
relevant to say on the on the future of today's physics, they cannot
miss, even if the relativistic framework would not embrace all
virtualities of the universe, it would give us the illusion that it
does, exactly as the physics of Maxwell and Kelvin did. The assertion
that no new discovery will never make it possible to shortcut the limits
of relativistic physics thus implies an act of faith. It supposes that
what is to demonstrate is certain, for it is quite obvious that
nonrelativistic or ultra-relativists phenomena remain to be discovered,
they are excluded by nature from the relativistic framework, exactly as
it was excluded from Maxwell's paradigm that one could transform a
material mass into electromagnetic waves. That did not prevent the
atomic bomb from exploding. But it required the discovered that Maxwell
had embraced only part of the phenomena.
The example of Maxwell
indicates that if facts not compliant with relativistic physics had
suddenly occurred in front of our eyes, they would appear at least as
phantasmagoric and absurd as the display at Hiroshima would have
appeared to Lord Kelvin, and probably much more. If, in addition, these
facts occurred in a fugitive and difficult to observe manner, physics
would be useful to us, not to study them, but to refute them. Common
sense even would invite us to such a rejection: to question the whole
body of our knowledge, one needs well proven facts. In the case of
Maxwell for example, one needed that black body radiation and
measurements of the absolute movement of the Earth in space contradict
all the existing predictions. Nothing, therefore, is more normal than
the denial expressed by so many scientists to of accounts which, taken
separately, have insufficient proof to convince, for to accept only one
of them, it is necessary to give up current physics.
If
extraterrestrial beings were here, they say, they would have contacted
us. We do not note nothing like that. Thus, they are not here.
We
never think about the strangeness and even the unfathomable in this
absence. We do not think of it for the same reason that the Romans never
worried about America: by provincialism and intellectual myopia.
Because we limit our reflexions with appearances and that all
appearances are deformed by the prospect. For Remus and Romulus, the
universe stopped with the Samnites and Albans, and the only concern of
the gods whom they adored was knowledge to which of these people they
were going to give the empire of the world, i.e. a small corner of the
Italian boot. During this time, China and India, quite as short-sighted
and provincial, were unaware that they would be one day conquered by a
civilization whose very existence was unknown to them.
However,
as we saw, stars as advanced as our Sun existed already there is billion
years; these stars (which we see) already had the planets
(astrometrical measurements show their presence), whereas our own Earth
did not exist yet. If civilizations as advanced as that of our twentieth
century existed already on these planets there billion years before,
that happened with them since? Why haven't they spread in space? Why
didn't they discover us? Why don't we see them?
Science-fiction
already produced thousands of books describing the arrival of
extraterrestrials on Earth. Their authors thought of everything. They
imagined all the possibilities. However nobody proposed satisfactory
explanation to this very stupid and well proven fact: we never saw any
extraterrestrial arrive.
In 1957, I had tried to consider all the
possible explanations of this extraordinary absence. Here they are in
their logical order:
1. terrestrial life is the only life in the universe;
2. of all the life in space, terrestrial life is the only one which evolved up to the human level;
3. of all the lifeforms having evolved up to our level, there is none which is more advanced than us in the conquest of space;
4. the conquest of space is limited to a distance lower than that which separates us from nearest superhuman civilization;
5. contact between different sentient species is impossible;
6. contact, though possible, is avoided;
7. contact is in secrecy;
8. contact is invisible.
Of
these eight assumptions, there is of course no way of knowing which is
the correct one. What can be done, however, is to follow the logic of
things such science shows us, to see where this logic leads to, and to
then confront the result of this speculation with what is really
observed.
The logic of things such as us science shows is
expressed in what Sebastian von Hoener called "the principle of
banality" (3): the man is not a miraculous being, but only the very
ordinary king of an ordinary planet revolving around an ordinary sun, in
an ordinary place of our galaxy, which a very ordinary galaxy.
Moreover, the moment that we currently live, if it is exceptionally
important in our particular history, is only an ordinary moment of the
history of the universe: such moments are, were and will be lived by a
crowd of other particular histories as ordinary as ours.
The
"principle of banality" is not universally shown: for example, we do not
have any factual proof that the human level is banal in the universe,
since we do not know for the moment of any other mankind than our
mankind.
But although it is not universally proven, the facts
teach on the other hand that, each time it can be tested, it is
regularly confirmed. And it was tested a very large number of times. It
was initially believed, for example, that our Earth was the center of
the world; then it was discovered that it was only a planet; it was said
afterwards that the center of the world is our Sun; but the Sun proved
to be only one banal star of G class; it was then declared that our Sun
was the only one to have planets, but soon it was discovered that almost
all the stars have some; then all went back to the Earth, which was
claimed to be exceptional by his constitution; but the observation of
stars in formation showed that this constitution was inevitable at a
certain distance from any star.
The principle of banality was
checked also for the constitution of our Sun, its age, its situation in
the galaxy, all its characteristics within its class, in the diagram of
Herzsprung-Russel, etc. The same applies to our galaxy.
The same
applies to all that can currently be observed and tested. The man can
obviously continue to assert a hypothetical singularity in all the
parameters of his condition which were not tested yet. It is with this
faith like with faith in Santa Klaus, whose non-existence is unprovable.
All that one can say, it is that each time one wanted to test the
reality of Santa Klaus or the singularity of man, neither Santa Klaus
nor a singularity were found.
We do admit however that the
principle of banality is proven only where it is proven, and,
consequently, it can be contradicted as soon as it is next tested by
this famous toss of the dice which abolishes the chance. We will limit
ourselves, as said above, to hypothetically follow logic to see where it
leads us, in order to possibly be able to test it once more.
Let
us first note that if Sebastian von Hoener had formulated its principle
one century ago, he would have saved to Lord Kelvin the blunder of his
announcement, a few years before Planck and Einstein, of the completion
of physics. The direction of the principle of banality is that any
singularity is illusory and ascribable only to our own ignorance, or, if
one prefes, with the relativity of our knowledge. To claim the
completion of physics (by definition as large an ambition as the
universe is large), it is to assert the most exorbitant singularity,
that which would place the author of the assertion at the top of any
possible knowledge.
The logic of the principle of banality
supposes that any knowledge, as advanced it would be, is at a banal
level of total knowledge, if such a total knowledge exists. In other
words, physics, and any other science having the whole universe for
object, will never be completed; there are perhaps absolute limits to
the possibilities of action of science and technique on the phenomena,
but if we suppose that these limits exist, we will not be able to ever
know if such particular limit against which we run up is really absolute
or if it only translates our ignorance. Consequently, a statement that
space flights or intergalactic (or even the crossing of some type of
scienc-fiction sub-space) are impossible, is nothing different than to
state that they are impossible for us, but we do not know if these are
possible or not to any other more advanced civilization than there ours.
However,
these voyages are impossible and even inconceivable for us. Thus, if
they are done nevertheless, those which achieve them are not men. They
exceed us more especially as what they do appears more inconceivable us.
The exploration of the Principle of banality engages us here on a way which points out something unpleasant to us.
If
we try to predict how beings who by principle are supposed to be more
advanced to us would appear when we observe them, won't we stumble in
the same traps and become victims of the same aberrations as the
dreamers of ancient Byzance disputing on the genre of the angels? Will
it be necessary, in the name of science, to recover all the treaties of
angelology and demonology which flowered at the Middle Age? The danger
was felt by a militant spokesman of rationalism (3).
To admit the
existence of beings whose psychic capacities, motives and techniques
would be partly incomprehensible to the man, he write, would allow to
rehabilitate God himself.
This author undoubtedly wants to
denounce, not the rehabilitation of God who, in any assumption, does not
care too much about that, but that of the theological speculations of
which Valéry said that "they would make us believe that God is stupid."
Actually,
it seems that it is very exactly the opposite. The principle of
banality brings us back from the temptation to which the medieval
dreamers yielded, but it is for diverting use from it and for showing us
its vanity. We are warned that if beings more evolved than man do
indeed exist, we have strictly and irremediably nothing to say about
what is more evolved with them. If man were not an ordinary being, if it
were at the very top of knowledge and intelligence, even the
rationalist author referred to above could not refuse him the right to
legitimately speculate about God and the angels. It is not the principle
of banality which rehabilitates discussions on the angels' gender, it
is the principle of Kelvin. D'Alembert gave an excellent anticipated
illustration of the principle of banality when he said that if men were
triangles, God would surely have three sides. But Kelvin, like the
modern refuters of the flying saucers, did not know how to resist
temptation to believe that the universe could be locked up forever in
the three sides which limited his own knowledge.
To admit the
banality of human knowledge is to recognize its relativity, and
consequently to reintroduce it in the same problematics as animal
knowledge. Admittedly, there is an abyss between man and the most
intelligent animals. But let's not forgot that this abyss was crossed
without discontinuity by the effect of an unperceivable progress in
connection with the genetic changes slowly accumulated since the
beginning of the life until Homo-sapiens.
If biological evolution
is a banal phenomenon, the abyss which separates us from the monkey (as
the one which separates the monkey from the dog) is of comparable
nature with the abyss which separates us to the supposed advanced
beings. To sustain that it is not no, is to cut off the man in
theological definitions. We do not dispute the legitimacy of these
definitions. We say that science develops another step. And we notice
that certain rationalist authors are very eager to evacuate God of their
cosmogony, in condition however that the man remains created after his
image.
We can say nothing on what separates us to the supposed
advanced beings. But there is a science which studies what separates man
from the animal: ethology. If there is an abyss, this science crosses
it in the direction which precisely interests us: when he studies the
animal, the ethologist in the same situation as, compared to us, an
extraterrestrial being is supposed to be. His science having no other
object than the relations between psychisms of various complexities, let
us examine some of the experiments where this diversity appears.
Here
we have for example an insect attracted by light (it is called
"photopositive"). When it is mislaid in a container whose transparent
bottom is directed towards a source of light, what does it do? If it
blindly obeys its phototropism, it will fly in direction of the light,
with obstination. And thus it is captured in the transparent walls, and
will die without never thinking of making a turn of a few centimetres,
which would free him again. It is an adventure in which we see every
day: insects stupidly flying against the pane of a window lit by the
sun, when it would be enough for them to temporarily turn the back to
the light to be saved by the nonenlightened corridor and to find light
at the price of a short turning.
The spider, which is capable of
much more complex and varied behaviors than the fly, not only does not
make this error, not only is able to escape its simplest tropisms
(because of course, it also has some), but moreover uses its superiority
to create with art the conditions according to which the fly will throw
itself infallibly in its web (4).
The interesting fact for us is
that the spider continues in peace its activities since million years
without the phototropic insects ever to come to the idea of a turning.
The superficial observer says that the fly is "stupid." He does not
wonder of what its "sillyness" consists of. The physiologist knows the
answer: it is that fly does not have a sufficiently complex central
nervous system to "conceive" a turning. To conceive this plan would
require a network of storage and data processing more complex than it
has and which, unfortunately for it, exists in the nervous system of the
spider (5). The flies whose spider makes its lunch are locked up
forever within a behavioral framework which delivers them without
defense to the tricks of their enemy.
But the spider, which lives
of its skill to manufacture imparables traps to the fly, also undergoes
the limitations of its own psychism and is used as prey by many
sphegides whose extraordinary talent to recognize the chart of a
territory astounds the naturalists.
The terrestrial living nature
entirely is thus a closed field where different psychisms clash without
never being able to come out of their limits, which are irremediably
traced by physiological complexity that the anatomy of each particular
species determines.
It is in extreme higher cases of the
animality, with monkeys and dolphins, that the most instructive
observations were made these last years (6).
When one puts one
these animals at the catches with a problem which exceeds only by a
little its capacities, it uses its more extraordinary intellectual
performances to try to solve it; if on the contrary the problem exceeds
its capacities too much, it is not perceived any more like a problem,
but only as a threat, and the behavior of the animal develops completely
randomly.
The monkeys studied by Cole (6) are well aware that
the situation in which they are put by the mischievousness of the
experimenter is unpleasant or threatening, but they are obstinent
"stupid" (like the fly), in their attempts to come out of there, to
precisely suppose that the causes of this situation does not exceed a
certain degree of complexity, that which a monkey brain can conceive.
They hopelessly make the inventory of their capacities of monkey and
take refuge in all the more primitive and summary reactions (escape,
combat) which they more highly feel the need for doing something,
whereas, from our point of view, a little reflexion would be enough to
abolish the difficulty.
For the monkey, the degree of complexity
where the solution is located is as if it did not exist. It is
irremediably inaccessible to him. We know why: the cerebral centers of
integration of the monkey (the neural network of its frontal lobes) are
not able to work out the models of activities required by the problem
more than the calculator of a self-service store cannot calculate a
derivative. It is not a matter of "sillyness," but a matter of
impossibility.
We mentioned above than this psychic limitation of
species is a universal fact within terrestrial lifeforms: thus, life
developed on our planet to the man inclusively, by the tireless
confrontation of all these limited psychisms.
Scientists know that. They hold it, and all their science theirs shows, for a fact of completely coarse obviousness.
The
relation of this psychic limitation of species to the complexity of the
nervous system is also perfectly demonstrated, even if it only is
partially explored. Martin Wells for example could gradually reduce the
psychic performances of cephalopodes which he studies in his laboratory
of Churchill College of Cambridge by electively paralysing their
integrating centers, one after the other, starting with most complex,
i.e. by going up their paleontological order of apparition from the most
recent to the most primitive. The pathology of the human brain shows
the same regression of our psychism, according to whether the lesions
destroy newer or older parts of the brain. It is a fact universally
attested with the terrestrial life.
Nothing certainly prohibits
to us, in the name of the principle of Kelvin, to claim that this
psychic limitation of species, universally attested in all animals up to
mankind, miraculously ceases to apply to mankind itself.
Owing
to the fact that the man is the most advanced being of this planet, no
known being can put him in the situation which the monkey of laboratory
experimenter Cole are confronted with. He can thus declare with impunity
that no thought could pose to him an irremediably insoluble problems by
the play of his own thought. Not only he can, but his entire
terrestrial experiment comes to confirm this opinion, and due, being the
most advanced, he never met a more advanced being which supercedes him
on Earth.
Let us notice that the tertiary primate from where the
line of Homo sapiens came out could have claimed the same. He, who could
neither control fire, neither manufacture a tool, neither to count the
days of its life, nor understand that when he had sex with its female,
she became fertilized, could also had a thought which could, without
fearing a denial, declare that he achieved the completion of the highest
thought, since it was the most advanced of the entire planet.
Two
short million years passed, and if Cole met this king of creation, he
would hasten to set up a cage for it in its laboratory to pose insoluble
problems to it. Insoluble, for this former king. Not for us who we
believe we cannot be beaten.
What authorizes the quaternary
primate, refuter of the flying saucers, to assert the final intellectual
supremacy, which the tertiary primate could assert already, but
wrongly, though as persuaded than we are to be right, and for identical
reasons? I do not know. But finally, our wise quaternary being claims
that the assumption that there may be a thought as impenetrable to their
as theirs was to the monkey is absurd and ridiculous. I submit to them:
you say that it is "irrational" to admit the possibility that there are
beings whose psychic capacities, mobiles and the techniques would be
incomprehensible to the man. As the presence of such beings in the
terrestrial environment would precisely suppose the reality of these
incomprehensible techniques (since you in the same way showed the
impossibility of such a presence), it follows that if, in spite of your
demonstration, the Earth were visited by extraterrestrial sentient
beings, it would show exactly the same relation than Cole had with his
monkeys.
I do not say that the Earth is visited by such a
thought. I only say, using your demonstration, that if this visit were
proven by the observation (which is the only way to get a positive
knowledge), the thought of our visitor could not be reduced to ours that
its technique could be reduced to our rockets. As much as their science
would contradict our science, as much would their psychism be advanced
in comparison with ours.
Admittedly, the contact is possible
between Cole and its monkey. It is possible with the help of a cage. It
is bilateral on the level of the monkey, i.e. that man, with the help of
a study full with traps and difficulties, can in extreme cases exchange
with the monkey all the "ideas" of the monkey (7). But this exchange is
unilateral on the level of the man who can explain to the monkey
neither what himself, man, is doing, neither why he does it. The
experiments of Jane Van Lawick Goodall in particular demonstrates that
contact is established only though domestication if it does not respect
the psychic limits of the animal.
Applied to man, a device of
this kind would promptly end to dehumanize it, since our species holds
all its dignity in its undomesticated history, and that this history was
born from our efforts against the unknown and the adversity.
For
what would our thought be used, if a communication with an
inexhaustible source of knowledge had suddenly spared us any effort and
any research? Is the adult human condition compatible with a regression
to infantile dependency? Isn't the adult thought not, on the contrary,
by definition, a nondependent thought?
If we follow the principle
of banality until the end, the human condition must be regarded as a
simple particular moment of any thought, from one end to another of the
universe, namely the moment when each planetary thought discovers the
vastness of space without having yet acquired the possibility of
reaching to it.
A crowd, perhaps an infinity of species, must be at this step in the infinite universe.
And the species (if they exist) which exceeded this stage must have an ethics towards them.
We
do not know anything of them, but we know enough about us to define,
from our point of view, that the first requirement of this Ethics it is
the respect of our reason and our freedom, and consequently the refusal
of contact.
If a higher thought than ours knows our existence and observes us, we will be able to ever know what it is.
And
if it respects us, it must leave us with our loneliness until our own
metamorphosis makes us able to reach them by ourselves, without the
burden of dependency.
Still considering the things from our point
of view, the best that this intelligence can do is to stimulate ours by
proposing problems to us, "a little higher than our possibilities," as
Cole in his experiments with his monkeys.
After twenty years of
studies and discussions, we believe that it is precisely what it does.
And we are struck to note that what seemed to us a challenge to reason
at the start appears by examination, in conformity with reason.
If
nobody had observed flying saucers, we should now wonder why. We would
be forced to imagine a very different universe than the one which
science discovers little by little, a universe in which man would be an
incomprehensible miracle, an "unsoundable joke," according to the words
of the astrophysicist Schkovski.
Is man this unsoundable joke? Or
does man occupy its small place, at the same time banal and priceless,
in a corner of the order of the things? Perhaps, we will be able to
answer this question when we know what the flying saucers are.
(1) See the Condon Report, p. 285.
(2)
A.G.W. Cameron, Interstellar Communication, New York, W.A. Benia
publisher, 1966, and the study by Sebastian Von Hoerner: The General
limits space travel ("Nature", vol. 137, July 6, 1962, pp. 18-23).
(3) La pensée, July-August 1961.
(3)
"Assumption of mediocrity" (I.S. Scieiovski and Sagan, Intelligent Life
in the universe, Holden-day, Londres 1966, p. 356 and following.).
(4)
See W.H. Torpe, Learning and instincts in animals (Methuen, London,
1963) and in R. Chauvin, Psychophysiologie (Paris, 1969, Masson), Vol.
Il. les chapitres consacrés au Labyrinthe, au détour et à
l'apprentissage.
(5) Joseph Altman, Organic fondation of animal behaviour (Halt, Rinhart and Winston, London, 1966), in particular chapter IV.
(6)
R.F. Ewer, Ethology of Mammals (Logos Press, London, 1968); M. Chance
et C. Jolly, Social Groups of Monkeys, Apes and Men (J. Cape, Londres,
1970); J. Cole, A Study of discrimination reverse learning in monkeys
(J. Compar, "Physiolog. Psychol.", 1951, vol. 44, pp. 467-472).
(7)
See essentially the wonderful sudies by J. Van Lawick, who managed to
live in the company of several spcies of apes, in natura ("Primate
Ethology", Weidenfeld and Nicholson, London, 1967).